top of page

Relatively Speaking

Writer's picture: Luke GirkeLuke Girke

Detractors of moral relativism, including the eminent philosopher Immanuel Kant, propound the existence of moral tenets that possess universal and objective validity, transcending individual or cultural paradigms. Kant's deontological ethical framework posits the presence of categorical imperatives, immutable moral principles that endure irrespective of situational context. Consider, for instance, the prohibition of acts such as murder and torture, widely deemed universally reprehensible due to their infliction of severe harm or death upon innocent individuals. These transgressions resonate with Kant's foundational principle, which advocates treating others as means to an end and as ends in themselves.


Articulated by critics like philosopher James Rachels, moral relativism stands vulnerable to logical incongruities. The contention that morality is wholly subjective engenders difficulties in appraising or adjudicating the actions of individuals or cultures without ensnaring itself in inherent contradictions. Rachels, for instance, contends that cultural relativism falters in its inability to furnish a basis for condemning practices such as female genital mutilation (FGM), as doing so would necessitate the acceptance of the moral legitimacy of such practices within particular cultures, rendering moral relativism an untenable doctrine.


Intellectual luminaries like Martha Nussbaum criticise moral relativism for its potential to impede moral advancement by dissuading critiques of deleterious cultural practices. Nussbaum contends that the absence of a framework for assessing actions predicated upon objective ethical principles could lead societies to exhibit diminished enthusiasm for reforming and enhancing their ethical standards. Historically, practices like slavery and discrimination persisted for centuries due to their cultural endorsement, but moral progress transpired when individuals and societies began to perceive these practices as ethically abhorrent, a development at odds with the premises of cultural relativism.


Philosophers exemplified by John Rawls argue that moral relativism threatens to erode the foundations of human rights and justice systems, often premised upon universal principles. Rawls' theory of justice underscores the significance of a "veil of ignorance," a hypothetical scenario wherein individuals construct an equitable society without knowledge regarding their personal or cultural attributes. Advocates of human rights, animated by Rawls' insights, posit the existence of ethical standards with global applicability, irrespective of cultural divergences. Rejecting the existence of such universal values can engender formidable impediments when confronting challenges such as genocide, torture, or discrimination on the international stage.


Cultural relativism, subject to critique by feminist theorists like Martha Nussbaum, can stifle censure of practices within a culture that may inflict harm or oppression, particularly upon marginalised demographics. Nussbaum contends that cultural relativism may arrest societal development by inhibiting external scrutiny and internal introspection. This posture could potentially obstruct endeavours aimed at extirpating practices such as female genital mutilation (FGM), which transgress individual human rights and well-being.


The critique articulated by philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche underscores how cultural relativism can erode individual moral autonomy. Nietzsche posits that cultural relativism implies that individuals lack a foundation for interrogating their culture's values and practices. This, Nietzsche argues, proves detrimental to personal maturation and ethical refinement, as it discourages critical cogitation and the capacity to make informed moral decisions rooted in individual discernment.


The demarcation between tolerance and relativism, elucidated by luminaries such as Karl Popper, merits elucidation. Critics contend that while tolerance remains indispensable for fostering harmonious coexistence among diverse cultures, it need not encompass the wholesale acceptance of all cultural practices as morally equivalent. Popper's exposition of the "paradox of tolerance" posits that tolerance should not extend to practices that promulgate intolerance themselves. Consequently, it is plausible to be tolerant of diverse cultures without embracing a relativistic stance on morality, a stance positing all cultural practices as morally indistinguishable.


Scholars of human rights, exemplified by Amartya Sen, mount challenges against cultural relativism's compatibility with the concept of universal human rights and shared ethical values. Sen posits that certain principles, encompassing the right to life, freedom from torture, and equality before the law, should universally apply to all individuals, irrespective of their cultural milieu. Cultural relativism may, therefore, undermine endeavours aimed at safeguarding these fundamental human rights, for it suggests that cultural customs can exonerate breaches of these rights.


Cultural relativism engenders internal discord when confronting ethical quandaries underpinned by intercultural clashes. To illustrate, it becomes an onerous task to condemn practices such as child marriage or FGM when cultural relativism is carried to its acme, given that these practices may be deeply entrenched within specific cultural milieus. Such inconsistency complicates the resolution of grave ethical dilemmas and the protection of vulnerable individuals, particularly in instances where cultural practices transgress human rights and individual welfare.




© 2025 The Girke Group Melbourne. 

Website Designed by Luke Girke in collaboration with The Girke Group Management.



Website

The information provided by The Girke Group (‘we’, ‘us’, or ‘our’) on http://www.girke.com.au (the ‘Site’) and our mobile application is for general informational purposes only. All information on the Site and our mobile application is provided in good faith, however we make no representation or warranty of any kind, express or implied, regarding the accuracy, adequacy, validity, reliability, availability, or completeness of any information on the Site our or mobile application. UNDER NO CIRCUMSTANCE SHALL WE HAVE ANY LIABILITY TO YOU FOR ANY LOSS OR DAMAGE OF ANY KIND INCURRED AS A RESULT OF THE USE OF THE SITE OR OUR MOBILE APPLICATION OR RELIANCE ON ANY INFORMATION PROVIDED ON THE SITE AND OUR APPLICATION. YOUR USE OF THE SITE AND OUR MOBILE APPLICATION AND YOUR RELIANCE ON ANY INFORMATION ON THE SITE AND OUR MOBILE APPLICATION IS SOLELY AT YOUR OWN RISK. 

 

Professional Liability

The Site cannot and does not contain medical/health, legal, and fitness advice. The medical/health, legal, and fitness information is provided for general informational and educational purposes only and is not a substitute for professional advice. Accordingly, before taking any actions based upon such information, we encourage you to consult with the appropriate professionals. We not provide any kind of medical/health, legal, and fitness advice. THE USE OR RELIANCE OF ANY INFORMATION CONTAINED ON THE SITE OR OUR MOBILE APPLICATION IS SOLELY AT YOUR OWN RISK. 

 

Testimonials  

The Site may contain testimonials by users of our products and/or services. These testimonials reflect the real-life experiences and opinions of such users. However, the experiences are personal to those particular users, and may not necessarily be representative of all users of our products and/or services. We do not claim, and you should not assume, that all users will have the same experiences. YOUR INDIVIDUAL RESULTS MAY VARY.  The testimonials on the Site are submitted in various forms such as text, audio, and/or video, and are reviewed by us before being posted. They appear on the Site verbatim as given by the users, except for the correction of grammar or typing errors. Some testimonials may have been shortened for the sake of brevity where the full testimonial contained extraneous information not relevant to the general public. The views and opinions contained in the testimonials belong solely to the individual user and do not reflect our views and opinions. We are not affiliated with users who provide testimonials, and users are not paid or otherwise compensated for their testimonials.

Blog

Articles on this website are not intended to diagnose, treat, cure, or prevent any diseases. The Therapeutic Goods Administration (TGA) and Food and Drug Administration (FDA) have not evaluated these articles. All information available on the website and blog is for educational purposes only. A qualified healthcare professional should be consulted before implementing any fitness, health, or nutritional protocol provided in the blog. Additionally, the articles containing material related to the law, legalities, or the legal profession are exploratory only and are not legal advice.
 

bottom of page